Free Essay

Mirror Neurons

In:

Submitted By JamaicaBev
Words 4877
Pages 20
Spring

12

Mirror Neurons In Motor and Social Acts
The authors who ushered in what might be considered the most critical finding of 21st century neuroscience to date—the discovery of mirror neurons (MNs)—contend that MNs underlie simulation theories of action understanding and mindreading (Gallese & Goldman, 1998); Gallese et al., (2004). The mechanism that allows mirroring of action is referred to as the ‘direct-matching hypothesis,’ (Rizzolatti et al., 2001), and the claim is based on the response properties of MNs in monkeys. The discovery of MNs is important in that if the implications of their function are properly understood, it lays a foundation for explanations of not only understanding of action and other minds (Gallese, 2003), but for other big questions, such as the evolution of language (Rizzolatti & Arbib, 1998). The concern of this paper is MN function as a feature at the core of the stronger claims. Alternative theorists challenge the characterization of the MN role as ‘mirroring’ action, as their findings show that mirroring cannot be direct and must rely on an interpretation of the observed action. They claim: a) MNs do not simulate with enough precision to be referred to as ‘mirroring,’ in which they are said to simulate an agent’s motor program onto the very same motor repertoire of an observer not performing the act; b) mirror neuron activation is predictive of action, not replicative; and c) the function of these neurons supports a model that is generative of top-down action understanding that is emulative, and formed outside the motor system, not embodied in the simulation of the motor act (Csibra, 2007). While attributions made for MNs are compelling in the philosophical accounts by Gallese (2001) and others, on close inspection unequivocal empirical evidence is sparse. The alternative model proposed has unanswered questions for the human mirrormatching theorists. Yet mindreading, which requires identifying and understanding others as similar to ourselves is heralded as the key to our evolutionary success (Tomasello, 2000).

Introduction An essential pre-condition to successful social interactions is the intrinsic capacity to recognize other-intentions (Sartori et al., 2011). The claim that we do so through observing the movements of others is the prevailing view, and yet gives rise to a multilayered controversy. The dominant view purports the function of mirror neurons (MNs) underlies third-person mindreading; ‘mindreading’ being the cognitive capacity to represent psychological states of the self and other, such as desires, beliefs, intentions, and feelings. There are three essential components to this view: ‘strict motor resonance,’ which posits that MN brain activity resonates between agent and observer, creating precisely matching neural motor patterns as they interact; ‘internal forward models’ which generate a postdictive observer understanding of agentintentions; and ‘embodied simulation’ wherein the intentions of others are gleaned by the observation of the movement of an agent. These advocates of intention-embedded motor processes deny the computational-representational view of human cognition as an instrument that transforms symbols using syntactic rules. Contesting this view are proponents of a contrasting, alternative model who instead propose that the task of MNs is to assess a prior representation of an agent’s intention and to predictively compute the motor command best suited to ensure the agent’s goals are reached (Jacobs, 2008). In this paper I will restrict the focus to the essential, underlying question at hand: how does an MN function? Solving this illuminates the inquiry into the further questions of if and how MNs contribute to our understanding of other minds. I will start by giving a brief background on MNs and the context for the opinions, then present the two opposing views in condensed form, and from there consider the supporting evidence on the points of disagreement. Ultimately I conclude that new research is needed; research that is inspired by new theoretical models, and seeks to falsify MNs as strict replicators, if only to better understand their nature.

2

View 1 (Vittorio Gallese, 2011) The prevalent view of how we understand the intentions of others is rooted in action as a relational concept. In this view, in the forward model of motor action, MNs are said to source an efference copy—an internal copy of the signal of a motor program—to estimate sensory outcomes of an action. In an agent’s brain canonical neurons (object-activated) translate features of an object that the agent wishes to act upon (e.g. a
Image: Csidra, 2007

bottle he wishes to grasp) into the best-fit motor program to

execute the action. MNs are activated by an efference copy of the motor plan and simulate the action program to ensure the intended goal is reached. As we observe the agent’s actions, our neural resonance mechanisms model the observed behavior for us internally—matching the motor commands to those we recruit when we ourselves perform the action—mapping the same neural substrate we use to do so. The MNs retrodictively create a representation of the agent’s intent (Gallese, 2011: 40-41). View 2 (Pierre Jacobs, 2008) Alternatively Jacobs (2008) theorizes that in line with inverse models of action, MNs in both an agent and observer’s brain will compute the motor commands to achieve the agent’s prior goals and intentions. In the agent this is done from an internally generated representation of the prior intentions, while
Image: Csibra, 2007

in the observer the representation of prior intentions is derived from perceptual cues. In this view visual analysis makes a contribution to interpreting actions and sequences, as shown by cell activation in the superior temporal sulcus (STS), which has perceptual but no motor properties.

3

As Csibra (2005) points out, prior to being transformed into motor code, in the visual system mid/high level interpretations of observed actions may contain goal assumptions that get incorporated in the motor code. Likewise actions may be filtered at this level into units of relevancy (e.g. non-grasping hand). The STS responds not only to body movements but important eye and head motion, including the target of visual attention (gaze) for which to date no MNs show a response. So the STS, reciprocally connected to the inferior parietal lobe (thus having a path to the pre-motor cortex), in this view is thought to make a contribution to generating an inner representation of an agent’s intentions. Rather than a retrodictive ‘action mirroring’ process that recovers the intention from coded action, Csibra (2005) calls this ‘action reconstruction’ as here the MN predicts the motor command needed to get to the goal.

In the Research - View 1 Between 1985 and 2000 a string of single-neuron studies in monkeys revealed a discrete subset of pre-motor and parietal neurons, dubbed mirror neurons, were activated both when the animal executed a motor act and when it observed the same act performed by others (Gallese, 2001). These were designated ‘mirror-neurons,’ requiring an action-object interaction (by monkey or human) in order to be discharged. The reasoning that led Gallese and Goldman (1998) to the view that MNs might underlie mindreading began with this discovery along with additional data from some other studies. For example, Fadiga et al. (1995) demonstrated that the observation of hand actions performed by others enlivened the same neural hand and arm substrates that were used when observing agents performed the same.

4

Two Computational Systems are presented: one that receives information about an action and outputs a goal for it (action- to-goal), and another one that generates the right action for the goal emerging at its input (goal-to-action).

View 1 (embodied)
Action to Goal
Auto-­‐‑Pre-­‐‑Reflexive Modeling View(Strict motor resonance adherence model) Mirror Neurons simulate a representation of the agent'ʹs intention from an a priori representation of the agent'ʹs motor command in accord with an internal forward model. • How? • Canonical neurons translate features of the target into the most suitable motor program enabling a successful action to be produced. • An efference copy of this signal is fed to mirror neurons which faciliate a simulation of the action program. • This simulation of the action is used to predict its consequences (goal). • MNs in an observer’s brain is taken to constitute an automatic mental simulation of the agent’s observed movements, enabling the observer to match the agent’s observed movements onto her own motor repertoire (without executing the movements in question). • The activity of MNs is seen as enabling the observer to represent the agent'ʹs intentions • Simulation Postdictive • Learning Imitative

View 2 (cognitivist)
Goal to Action
Computational-­‐‑Representational View
(Uses logical chains of related MN activity) Mirror Neurons compute a representation of the agent’s motor command from an a priori representation of the agent’s intention, in accordance with an internal inverse model. • How? • Neurons in the STS respond to a vast array of eye and head movements and full body movements (including locomotion), a purely perceptual network of ‘social perception’ involving the STS, the amygdala and the orbito-­‐‑ frontal cortex • The representation of an agent’s prior intention, might arise in an observer’s brain as a result of this activity of the STS, which is reciprocally connected to the inferior parietal cortex, and is known to contain neurons with purely perceptual and no motor properties. • MNs in the observer’s brain predictively compute the best motor command suitable to satisfy the agent’s intention. • Simulation Predictive • Learning Emulative

Figure 1 Distillation of the two approaches. View 1 - Gallese, 2011, View 2 - Jacobs, 2008

5

Buccino et al. (2001) used fMRI in a study that showed that the observation of hand, mouth or foot during both transitive and intransitive actions created a corresponding engagement of somatotopic premotor cortex regions in the observer. This did not occur during observation of the same but motionless body parts. Corroborating this evidence that intentions or goals are gleaned though observation of motor action, distinct mental resonance mechanisms were revealed in two contrasting pathological examples. ‘Echopraxia’—the impulsive imitation of others’ movements—demonstrates that strict imitation uninhibited by thought may be possible. ‘Imitation behavior,’ a condition resulting from a lesion to the orbito-frontal cortex, led to the imitating of a goal by using an identical action rather than the one observed. This showed that a goal could be deduced from observation of motor action (Gallese, 2001). The hypothesis described as View 1 above was in part motivated by the need for a more comprehensive account for understanding “intended, mind-driven behavior,” as the researchers do not find that the visual coding of a stimulus accounts for it (Gallese, 2001: 35). A problem for visual analysis has been the question of how the neurons involved bind with sufficient complexity to promote understanding of the meaning of an action. By extending the visual hypothesis—a visual analysis of elemental action formation, with no motor involvement—to include motor synergistic action with sensory binding, a basis may be formed for action understanding, called the direct-matching hypothesis. Here, higher-order visual neurons combine the output of neurons responsive to both the observation of an arm reaching and the direction of gaze. For example, in studies with monkeys, the neurons activate when a monkey observes an actor reaching, but only when the actor’s gaze is also the apple (target) being reached for. Beyond helping code motor acts, MNs enable imitation in this view, and as imitation normally

6

happens for social reasons (e.g. for learning), the mirror system is further suggested as underlying other cognitive strategies, such as mindreading (Rizzolati, 2001)). To compound the earliest findings, a study by Meltzoff (1995) had adults execute and display goal-directed acts so that infant toddlers of eighteen months could re-create them. An example from the study was of an adult demonstrating trying to pull apart a toy dumbbell, but without success. The toddlers were able to re-enact the failed attempt. However when the children observed a mechanical device attempting to pull apart the dumbell they were unable to duplicate the effort. From this authors took it that in order to understand and mimic the intended goal of an observed action, a link must exist between the observed and observer. The proposal by these researchers is that this link is formed by the embodiment of the intended goal in the action, shared by the two parties. While the data from these experiments is considered valid, it is the construction of the View 1 hypothesis that has been criticized by the alternative theorists. Primarily this is because further studies have revealed evidence that questions the three primary assertions required to operationalize the view. In sum, the authors of View 1, the most widely accepted view, propose that the fundamental function of MNs is mindreading. This stronger claim represented by the direct-matching hypothesis leads to philosophical questions about whether a belief can be formed about another’s psychological state, via an experiential event that is not mediated by mental activity. Can a non-conceptual grasp of another’s mind (auto-simulated) even be categorized as third-person mindreading (Jacobs, 2008)? These claims have led to evidentiary disagreement of the three main features for the View 1 model by advocates of View 2. As discussed below these are: strict motor resonance, retrodictive representation in the internal forward models, and embodied simulation.

7

In the Research - View 2 I. Strict Motor Resonance Based on earlier evidence the most fundamental aspect of MNs was presumed to be the strict congruence between their motor and perceptual properties. Gallese and Goldman (1998: 498) had surmised that because MNs are a resonance tool they represent a neural basis and phylogenetic predecessor for mindreading. Initially, the same MNs had been found to fire both during execution and observation of an act of grasping (Jacobs, 2008). Several studies took place in 2005 with the goal of extending MN activity beyond recognizing the motor act to representing an agent’s intention. While this connection was made, the studies also brought new evidence to light in two primary areas seen as inconsistent with a strict resonance model of perceptual and motor properties. These are addressed below as: i) The Hierarchical Structure of Intentions; and ii) The Model of Chains of Logically Related MNs. i. Hierarchical Structure of Intentions A hierarchical structure of intentions distinguishes between a basic and non-basic act (Jacob, 2008, citing Goldman, 1970). The activation of MNs depends not only on the presence of goals, but may also fire preferentially according to the further, higher-level goals of an agent. In a Fogassi et al. (2005) study where monkeys were trained to perform two actions, some MNs showed more activation when a monkey grasped an object “to eat,” as compared to grasping the object “to place” into a container. Depending on the soon-to-be-taken action separate sets of MNs in the inferior parietal lobule fired. These neurons responded similarly when the monkey observed the same actions performed by an experimenter. Yet the first segment of the actions, the grasping, was shown to be without demarcation in kinematics—geometric motor positioning—indicating the MNs take into account the further goal and not just the perceived action (Csibra, 2007). In an fMRI experiment of like design but with humans, Iacoboni et al.

8

(2005) found that the MN firing in the right inferior frontal areas showed a far stronger bias for the “grip to drink” over the “grip to clean” condition. According to Searle (1983) agents have networks of “nested” intentions. Turning on a light when you want to read a book and don’t believe you have enough light is a non-basic act, as it will be attained through a series of basic discrete acts. Further, since your belief isn’t an actual fact, intentions can’t be anticipated. Therefore intentions are in relation to motor acts on a many-to-one basis. Perceiving a goal is more abstract that acting on a target. Jacobs (2008) discredits strict motor resonance finding it “lacks the resources to bridge the gap between representing an agent’s motor intention and representing her higher-level intentions” (Jacobs, 2008: 208). ii. Model of Chains of Logically Related MNs Rather than sheer replication (strict congruence of motor resonance), MN thinkers now subscribe to the idea of chains of ‘logically related’ MNs. As Iacoboni et al. (2005: 533) stipulate, the relation between pairs of MNs in a chain is inductive, not strictly logical, saying,
“... the present findings strongly suggest that coding the intention associated with the actions of others is based on the activation of a neuronal chain formed by mirror neurons coding the observed motor act and by ‘logically related’ mirror neurons coding the motor acts that are most likely to follow the observed one, given the context.”

Fogassi found 65% of MNs during grasping tasks are modulated by the more complex action of which the movement is only a part. The experiments do not show that motor contagion underlies action understanding, which as described is the representation of an agent’s prior intention. Rather than replicating the observed motor act we find MNs in the role of allowing the observer to predict an agent’s next act by combining the observation of the motor act and contextual clues (Jacobs, 2008). Csibra (2007) finds the most compelling evidence against strict motor resonance is the fact that there are only degrees of similarity between the act and observing the act (ie. when a monkey acts vs. when it observes an experimenter in the same act). In a review of the

9

studies, Csibra (2007) found the following: a) 19-41% of MNs—about one-third—show a oneto-one congruence between visual and motor cell properties for action category (e.g. grasp) and manner of execution (e.g. grasp type); b) 21-68% of MNs respond to two or more types of observed actions (e.g. grasping by hand or mouth), also termed “broadly congruent” MNs which make up the bulk of all MNs; and c) 10% of MNs with no relation being found between the two. Based on this meta-evidence, if monkeys relied on direct matching of action to goals, they would consistently misapprehend what they were seeing. This low visuo-motor congruence in the research can perhaps better be explained by action prediction which does not require strict replication, while extracting goals from action coding does. II. Retrodictive Representation Internal model systems are a critical concept to understanding motor control system

design and operation. Basically there are two types, forward and inverse models, which work together to compute the input that a system requires in order to attain the sought-after output. Forward models estimate the contribution needed to move to the next state from the current one, summing up the causal relationships amongst all the system inputs. By contrast, inverse models deliver the final motor command that will enact the change, controlling the desired transition (Wolpert et al., 1998). Gallese’s hypothesis has been framed using the logic of forward models. These are defined as ‘forward’ because they can capture the causal relationship of actions, as signaled by an efference copy, and from there estimate outcomes of motor commands. Essential to the success of the View 1 scenario, this idea conflicts with the typical flow of internal forward models for motor control. i. Internal Motor Models Essentially, forward models compute the sensory consequences of an action from a representation of the motor command while inverse models compute motor commands sufficient

10

to enact the agent’s prior intention (Jacobs, 2008). Blakemore and Decety (2001) hypothesize that an observer could use a forward internal model of action to retrodict an agent’s intention from his observed movements. Yet Csibra (2007) found that the retrodictive account has two difficulties when positioned in the forward model: first, it reverses the flow of information that is characteristic of computations executed by this model; and second, the account under-represents the complexity of computation needed to map an underlying intention from an observed movement. As discussed, the same movement can be applied toward many intentions. Of primary consideration is that an observer does not access an efference copy of the agent’s motor command as the agent does. So in this view the claimed tension is that two separate activations—the internally generated activation of MNs in an agent’s brain and the externally generated activation of MNs in an observer’s brain—make a contribution to the agent’s goal representation. In this event, the computation would therefore be predictive in the agent’s case and retrodictive in the observer’s case. So it becomes difficult to reconcile this asymmetry in a unified model. Jacobs (2008) asks us to resolve whether MNs function predictively as the new model of logically related MNs would imply, or whether MNs function retrodictively (in accordance with Gallese and Goldman’s views). In the case of non-human primates, researchers stress the value of anticipating a conspecific’s next move so the observing animal can prepare a reaction (Gallese and Goldman, 1998: 495-6). They don’t focus on the importance of retrodicting the conspecific’s former intention nor do they address the inhibitory skills that would be required for retrodiction, which has not yet been established in non-human primates.

11

III. Embodied Simulation View 1 authors distinguish between an engaged and a disengaged understanding of an agent’s action based on motor resonance. But as Jacobs (2008) points out, it is quite a jump from there to making the further—and much bigger—claim that motor resonance also automatically reveals the contents of an agent’s mind. View 2 proponents fault the latter assertion because simply matching an observed movement onto one’s motor substrate is not enough to know what an agent has in mind, nor have experimental results shown that MN activity generates an account of an agent’s prior intention. To accord with forward models of action it is proposed that an agent is able to predict the sensory consequences of his soon to be realized action via an efference copy of his own motor instructions. Yet an observer, unlike the agent, does not receive an efference copy of the agents agent’s motor program. So how could embodied simulation enable activity of MNs in an observer’s brain to yield the goal of the impending movement of an acting agent? i. Perceptual or Contextual Clues Researchers Jacob and Jeannerod (2005) and many others use evidence from developmental psychology to show that an observer is able to understand an agent’s prior intention without first mapping an agent’s motor command to her neural substrate. In experiments children from nine months to adult will assign and describe the emotions and social goals of a simple moving geometrical shape that has no human features (Jacob, 2008: 206-208). It is clear that infants show a consistent preference for “helping” as opposed to “hindering” shapes, yet ascertaining the intent of a triangle or square is clearly not due to use of motor simulation of non-biological movement (Kuhlmeier et al., 2003). In the Fogassi et al. (2005) and Iacoboni et al. (2005) experiments discussed above it was

12

shown that correlations exist between MN activity and the contextual cues of the scene. As noted, when the monkey sees an experimenter grasp a piece of food in order to eat it, neurons fire, yet MNs would not activate without any object involved when the experimenter mimicks the grasp to eat. Since goal hypotheses are only generated for meaningful actions, this indicates that the goal of the action is understood, without simulation. So, if only actions with clear outcomes are simulated by MNs, then simulation is not involved in the judgment of determining whether an action has a goal, which contradicts the evidence as interpreted in support of simulation theories. If MN simulation is involved in MN function, the simulation observed in the monkey is because of his having understood a goal, and not because he comprehends the goal due to his having simulated the action.

Conclusions First, I introduced the topic under conjecture from neuroscience about the role of motor action in mindreading, involving MNs. Next, I distilled these to a diagram showing two theoretic views, describing their discrete characteristics and how they claim to represent the function of MNs. In order to answer the question of whether motor action has a role in mindreading, from an evidence-based perspective I’ve explored the question of how MNs function, which is the critical underlying component for simulation-based theories. In doing so I’ve outlined the main components behind Gallese and Goldman’s (1998) influential idea that MNs simulate actions between individuals in order to yield intentions and goals. I’ve also represented the alternative view that arises in the most basic sense from the fact that MNs were first found in in macaque monkeys, yet we are short on proof of mindreading in monkeys. Until about 2005 most studies in the wake of the excitement following the discovery of MNs were designed with the original premise in mind, seeking to further the hypothesis of the

13

original authors of View 1 above. But studies designed in this way have done little to enhance actual knowledge. The results of these experiments have led the movement of theorists to endorse a new model, based on chains of logically related MNs as outlined in View 2. In considering both views complementary points were discussed in the research analysis of this paper. Here I summarized the evidence that shows the inconsistency of a strict resonance model of the activity of MNs based on the hierarchy of intentions, and the new findings for logically related MNs, shown to at best predict an agents motor intention, not social intention. The second point highlighted was the tension between computational resources afforded by the theory of internal forward models and a retrodictive process for MNs used to compute an agent’s intention. Instead, it has been proposed that, using an internal inverse model, MNs compute a representation of the agent’s motor command from a prior representation of the agent’s intention. The third point discussed in the research section of the paper is the experimental failure to provide an evidentiary basis for MN activity as a representation of the agent’s prior intention through embodied motor simulation. Rather, the evidence seems at least in part to agree with the alternative evaluations in which MN activity presupposes a representation of the agent’s intention using a perception of contextual cues. The alternative account does affirm the value of MNs in the social cognition of primates, as it gives weight to MN contribution to an onlooker's ability to estimate a conspecific’s next motor act (Jacobs, 2008). From this I conclude that before we can explain how we ascribe intention in a system that relies on MNs, new foundational research is needed to understand their function. It might be most fruitful to attempt to falsify the alternative view—View 2 above—since so much experimental work in support of View 1 has yielded few steps forward.

14

References Blakemore, S. and Decety, J. (2001). From the Perception of Action to the Understanding of Intention. Neuron, Vol. 42:323–334. Accessed online Feb 23, 2012. Gallese, Vittorio.Eagle, Morris N. Migone, Paolo. (2007). Intentional Attunement: Mirror Neurons and the Neural Underpinnings of Interpersonal Relations. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association. Sage Publications. Accessed online Feb. 26 2012.

15

Gallese, Vittorio. (2001). The ‘Shared Manifold’ Hypothesis From Mirror Neurons To Empathy. Journal of Consciousness Studies, Vol. 8, No. 5–7:33–50. Accessed online. < http://philpapers.org/rec/GALTSM > Iacoboni, Marco. Molnar-Szakacs, Istvan. Gallese, Vittorio. Buccino, Giovanni. Mazziotta, John C. Rizzolatti, Giacomo. (2005). Grasping the Intentions of Others with One’s Own Mirror Neuron System. PLoS Biology March 2005 Volume 3, Issue 3: 05290535.Accessed online Feb 23, 2012. Jacob, Pierre. (2007). Replies to our Critics. Psyche: Volume 13, Issue 2: 1-11. Accessed online Feb. 24, 2012. < http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/> Jacob, Pierre. (2008). What Do Mirror Neurons Contribute to Human Social Cognition? Volume 23, Issue 2:145–255. Mind and Language. Accessed online Feb 20, 2012. Kuhlmeier, V. Wynn, Karen. Bloom, Paul. (2003. Attribution of Dispositional States by 12Month-Olds. Psychological Science, Vol. 14, No. 5: 402-408. Accessed online Mar. 15, 2012. < http://www.jstor.org/stable/40064159> Pierno. Ansuini. Castiello. (2007). Motor Intentions versus Social Intentions: One System or Multiple Systems? Psyche: Volume 13, Issue 2: 1-10. Accessed online Feb. 24, 2012. Sartori, Luisa. Becchio, Cristina. Castiello, Umberto. (2011). Cues to intention: The role

16

of movement information. Cognition: Volume 119, Issue 2, May 2011: 242–252. Elsevier Ltd. Accessed online Feb. 23, 2012. Rizzolati, G. Arbib, M. (1998). Language Within Our Grasp. Trends in Neurosciences, Volume 21:188–194. Accessed online March 10, 2012. < http://www.sciencedirect.com.ezpprod1.hul.harvard.edu/science/article/pii/S0166223698012600> Rizzolatti, Giacomo. Fogassi, Leonardo. Gallese,Vittorio. (2001). Neurophysiological Mechanisms Underlying the Understanding and Imitation of Action. Nature Reviews. Neuroscience. Volume 2(9): 661-70. Accessed online Feb 22, 2012. < http://ukpmc.ac.uk/abstract/MED/11533734> Rizzolatti, Giacomo. Fogassi, Leonardo. Gallese,Vittorio. (2006). Mirrors In the Mind. Scientific American 295: 54-61. Accessed online Feb 24, 2012. Wolpert, D.M. Kawato, M. (1998). Multiple paired Forward and Inverse Models for Motor Control. Neural Networks Volume 11: 1317–1329 Accessed online Feb 24, 2012 < http://www.sciencedirect.com.ezpprod1.hul.harvard.edu/science/article/pii/S0893608098000665>

17

Similar Documents

Premium Essay

Mirror Neuron Theory

...symptoms of ASD. The discrepancy in results found in studies of the mirror neuron theory of ASD, could be the result of difficulty with imitation amongst those diagnosed with ASD, supporting their theory with results found by Williams, Whiten and Singh (2004), in a systematic review of twenty-one studies on imitation in ASD, fourteen found evidence of imitative deficits which suggests that generally children diagnosed with ASD performed worse on imitative tasks. However Williams et al. (2006) found that task performance was close to 100% with only two subjects making minor errors on two separate occasions, thereby clearly not having difficulty imitating. Fan et al. (2010) however did find that participants in the ASD group failed to imitate observed actions during execute conditions, while still presenting with intact mu-suppression and use this as strong evidence against the broken mirror theory of...

Words: 1494 - Pages: 6

Free Essay

Broken Mirrors

...Broken Mirror: The Mirror Neuron System and the Salience Landscape Dysfunction Pamela H. Crittenden University of Maryland University College The Mirror Neuron System and the Salience Landscape Dysfunction This paper will summarized and critique the important points discussed by Vilayanur S. Ramachandran and Lindsay M. Oberman in the article “The Theory of Autism”. Support and expansion of the ideas presented will be discussed. Several points in the article will be evaluated. Two theories that were prevalent during their studies to help explain and or determine the cause of Autism were the Mirror Neuron Dysfunctions and Disrupted Salience Landscape Theory. To begin it is important to define what is meant by Autism. It is a genetic disorder that plagues a small portion of Americans. Children diagnosed with Autism are unable to carry on normal conversations and tend to remove themselves from any chance of social contact. Although they may experience different types of emotions such as fear and pleasure they also experience poor language, lack of eye contact and social isolation. As stated by the author (Ramachandran and Oberman, 2006) Patricia M. Rodier believes that “susceptibility to autism is inherited” and her theory is based on a “newly discovered class of nerve cells in the brain called Mirror Neurons” (Ramachandran and Oberman, 2006, p.64). These nerve cells take on the same characteristics of an Autistic...

Words: 1112 - Pages: 5

Free Essay

Food Preservatives

...“Clear thinking requires peace of mind rather than intelligence.” ~Meredith Forder … When it comes to making the right choices in life, mere intelligence will not guarantee the best result. This fact is exemplified by the problems of obesity, anxiety, stress, addictions and depression among highly intelligent people. At Clear Thinking we believe that many of life’s problems can be solved by simply learning how to think clearly—how to keep your mind calm, focused and within your control. Critical thinking...the awakening of the intellect to the study of itself.  Critical thinking is a rich concept that has been developing throughout the past 2500 years.  The term "critical thinking" has its roots in the mid-late 20th century.  We offer here overlapping definitions, together which form a substantive, transdisciplinary conception of critical thinking. Critical Thinking as Defined by the National Council for Excellence in Critical Thinking, 1987 A statement by Michael Scriven & Richard Paul, presented at the 8th Annual International Conference on Critical Thinking and Education Reform, Summer 1987.  Critical thinking is the intellectually disciplined process of actively and skillfully conceptualizing, applying, analyzing, synthesizing, and/or evaluating information gathered from, or generated by, observation, experience, reflection, reasoning, or communication, as a guide to belief and action. In its exemplary form, it is based on universal intellectual values that...

Words: 3850 - Pages: 16

Free Essay

Gandwun Ki Baraat

...The neurons that shaped civilizations I'd like to talk to you today about the human brain, which is what we do research on at the University of California. Just think about this problem for a second. Here is a lump of flesh, about three pounds, which you can hold in the palm of your hand. But it can contemplate the vastness of interstellar space. It can contemplate the meaning of infinity, ask questions about the meaning of its own existence, about the nature of God. 0:34And this is truly the most amazing thing in the world. It's the greatest mystery confronting human beings:How does this all come about? Well, the brain, as you know, is made up of neurons. We're looking at neurons here. There are 100 billion neurons in the adult human brain. And each neuron makes something like 1,000 to 10,000 contacts with other neurons in the brain. And based on this, people have calculatedthat the number of permutations and combinations of brain activity exceeds the number of elementary particles in the universe. 1:01So, how do you go about studying the brain? One approach is to look at patients who had lesions in different part of the brain, and study changes in their behavior. This is what I spoke about in the last TED.Today I'll talk about a different approach, which is to put electrodes in different parts of the brain, and actually record the activity of individual nerve cells in the brain. Sort of eavesdrop on the activity of nerve cells in the brain. 1:22Now, one recent discovery...

Words: 1526 - Pages: 7

Free Essay

Yawning: the Power of a Single Word

...Yawning: The Power of a Single Word Intro: The power of a single word…one of life’s greatest mysteries. The ability to affect an entire crowd by uttering a distinct expression…do you know what word I’m talking about? It’s the word… Yawn. Believe it or not, yawning is one of the most googled phenomenons in the world. As a frequent yawner, I often question the mysterious bodily function. Without thinking about it, I can see or hear someone yawn, yearn to replicate the action, and before I know it, my mouth is agape. In fact, I’ve caught myself yawning involuntarily while talking on the phone to some of my most exciting friends. I’m pretty sure what I heard at the other end of the phone was a contagious yawn from the ever-so entertaining counterpart. All of you have experienced yawning, but many do not know its purpose, which is why I am here to inform you about why we yawn, why it is contagious, and how it benefits the body. Body: There are several reasons why we yawn, and those reasons have puzzled scientists for years. After completing many experiments, Andrew C. Gallup, a postdoctoral research associate at Princeton University, concluded that yawning cools the brain. Gallup explains to WebMD that when you begin to yawn, the stretching of your jaw increases blood flow in the neck, face, and head. The deep inhalation of breath that comes with a yawn drives the flow of spinal fluid and blood to the brain. Cool air that is breathed in lowers the temperature of these...

Words: 1237 - Pages: 5

Free Essay

Tut 2

...Chicks behavioural response to external Stimuli Devon Maxwell Anderson 17586704 BScAgric, Animal Production Systems and Aquculture, Stellenbosch, South Africa Abstract As animals age they develop ways to best handle situations they encounter. The experiment was divided into two parts. For both parts we investigated the behavioural reactions of 1-2 day old chicks to external stimuli. Part 1 we noted any physical responses to the stimuli whereas in part 2 we noted the chick’s average cheeps per minute when encountering the stimuli. When examining the final results of the experiment it is plain enough to see the effects of the stimuli on the chicks. For part 1 there was only an average of 1 chick showing any form of response to the stimuli of the same size and colour whereas the stimuli that received the most behavioural reaction was that of the sight of another chick with an average of 2.7. For part 2 the highest value recorded was when the chick was left alone without any stimuli, with an average of 77.4 cheeps per minute. The lowest response was when a second chick was used as a stimulus with an average of 32.4 cheeps per minute being recorded. Looking at these results it is easy to interpret that the chicks are less distressed by the presence of other chicks and seek comfort and security in groups. Introduction Naturally all living things adapt to best suite their environment. Evolution is loosely defined as the selection of animals with an increased fitness or possession...

Words: 1474 - Pages: 6

Free Essay

Business

...Inner self Mirrors exist to show our physical appearance, but nothing beyond that. Only our views, ideas, and actions can truly represent who we are and what makes us so different from one another. The true value of a person is discovered in those glimpses of light in the midst of adversity and darkness. Those traits that are highly praised are also learned and acquired in those darkest moments. The one I hold most precious, over any other trait, is the quality of honesty. Honesty is to tell the truth, to believe the truth, and to act the truth when the opportunity arises. Integrity matters most when it is difficult to act nobly. I learned to be honest by admitting that I did not know what the truth was, even though I might have, or by choosing to appear ignorant rather than condemning. When I was younger, my mind was full of assumptions. I was always so quick to judge and blame, but I soon learned that assumptions without proof were the same as lies. By hurting others in those dark moments of doubt and injustice, I learned to tell the truth as I saw it and not as I wanted it to be. The best part about honesty is that if you see yourself as you truly are, then you can shape who you will become. Pride swells within me because I believe the most sought after quality in individuals is honesty. I strive to bring positive change to myself and the people around me, so I volunteer myself as an advocate for integrity. My real character shows through my actions and beliefs, and...

Words: 371 - Pages: 2

Free Essay

What Does the Mirror Stands for in “Beware: Do Not Read This Poem” by Ishmael Reed.

...What does the mirror stands for in “Beware: Do Not Read This Poem” by Ishmael Reed. Ishmael Reed is known for his satirical works challenging American political culture, and highlighting political and cultural oppression. In Beware: Do Not Read This Poem Reed protests against cultural dominance. Culture is a part of people, and language and art are parts of culture. And in this poem Reed talks about how people are made by cultures and lost to other cultures. However, Reed’s rightness of cultural protest is not of concern here, rather, the symbolic presentation of the mirror is under scrutiny here; and it can be said that the mirror represents art, literature and strikingly the poem itself. The poem starts with how an old woman becomes obsessed with mirrors, and grows isolated from the community, and how she abandons her old life and finds a new life among her mirrors, by disappearing herself within it. By this old woman’s story poet recalls the enchanting effects of literature and art on a reader. Poet rejects the idea of art and literature as a simple mirror reflecting life, and rather, claims it as a living experience. One finds reflection of his own life in literature, like the mirror, and gets lost in his imagination. At times, literature creates a whole new world, a world where things are very different, sometimes surreal, yet a reader finds reality in it, as it is really happening; and as he moves deeper into the story, the imagination becomes so strong that he begins...

Words: 528 - Pages: 3

Free Essay

Mirroring

...Mirror Realism Matt Leonard Let’s suppose that spacetime substantivalism is true. In other words, space- time regions exist independently of the objects that occupy them. They shouldn’t be thought of as mere ‘things’ or ‘events’ which happen to stand in spatiotemporal relations.1 Even with such an assumption, there is a lot to disagree about. And so, for the moment, let’s make a few more assumptions: let’s suppose that (1) material objects exist independently of spacetime re- gions (i.e., material objects are not identical to spacetime regions) and (2) material objects are exactly located at certain spacetime regions. Given this setup, it seems right to say that material objects and spacetime regions pos- sess mereological and topological properties, and enter into mereological and topological relations. Now consider the following question about the relation- ship between spacetime and material objects: are material objects a perfect mirror of their spacetime regions? We might ask: if two objects share some mereotopological relation (for instance, if one is a part of the other, or if one is connected to the other), does it follow that the regions of space at which the objects are located, share the same relation? Similarly, if two regions of space are related in some mereotopological way, are the objects located at those regions, related in the same way? If an object x is a proper part of some other object y, does it follow that the location, lx, of the former object is a proper...

Words: 3251 - Pages: 14

Free Essay

Extraction of Light

...theoretical meanings are also left to figure out, to have a small brainstorming at this moment is quite timely I suppose. It just happens to be the mid-point of combining Barbara’s DBR mirror with Lucie’s photonic crystal coupling system. By now, we’ve got three different DBRs (375nm, 620nm, 850nm and the gradient will be fabricated after this meeting) and each mirror has two types: 6 & 8 layers. Several optical measurements (Carry 50) and curves of calibration (TiO2-Eu(TTA)3 layer thickness) will be showed as flowing which are open for discussion. Hope this meeting will assess the work finished so far and give a clear direction for the further steps. II. DBRs The optical measurement of these mirrors is operated on Carry 50 and the corresponding simulation is carried out on Matlab (Reticolo). a. b. c. Figures a, b, c are DBRs of wavelengths 375nm, 620nm and 850nm. Curves left are optical measurement of transmission by Carry 50, curves right are the simulation associated. The discrepancies between the optical measurement and simulation by Matlab is mainly because for the Matlab simulation, it assumes that for a wavelength inferior to 420nm, all the wave will be absorbed by the glass which is not true compared to the optical measurement. Meanwhile a slightly deviation between the same type of mirror ( e.g, DBR 6C 375-1 & DBR 6C 375-2) in the optical measurement is possibly due to the fact that...

Words: 552 - Pages: 3

Free Essay

Captain Philips

...By: Sanabil Sajid Submitted To: Mr. Triantafillou Room: 211 Class: SNC2D3-04 Due Date: 08/01/2016 By: Sanabil Sajid Submitted To: Mr. Triantafillou Room: 211 Class: SNC2D3-04 Due Date: 08/01/2016 CONCAVE MIRRORS CONCAVE MIRRORS __________________ __________________ How does the distance of the object from a concave mirror affect the size and orientation of the image? 1) COVER PAGE • Use blank paper (not lined) • Put the Lab or Investigation Number in the center of the page and underline it • Put the Title of the Lab underneath it with CAPITALIZED LETTERS and underline it • Put your Name, Teacher’s Name, Your Class, and Due Date on the bottom right corner of the cover page • Put a list of your Group Members (not including yourself) on the bottom left corner of the cover page • No pictures or drawings should be on the cover page (front or back) 2) LAB WRITE-UP • If typed, use blank paper (not lined); if written, use lined paper • Put the Lab or Investigation Number on the top left of the first page and underline it • Put the Title of the Lab on the top middle of the first page, CAPITALIZED, and underline it • The lab write-up should be printed, handwritten or typed neatly • Must include ALL of the following headings (which are underlined) Problem: (Purpose / Question) • Write down the purpose of the lab; what you are trying to determine • This should be done in one sentence • Can be written as a question • Sometimes...

Words: 414 - Pages: 2

Free Essay

Animal

...to be around. But scientists say there's a lot more to these animals, and they're just beginning to understand the intricate thinking of these so-called, big-brained mammals. Here you go, Nani. Good girl. We came here to the Baltimore Aquarium to see just how intelligent dolphins are. You see them playing with their trainers all the time, but scientists who study them say there's a lot more happening there than just play, that their intelligence actually rivals ours. Here you go. To see up close what has scientists so excited, we climb down into a tiny underwater lab with a window into the aquarium, where scientist Diana Reiss puts a two-way mirror up against the glass. DIANA REISS, SCIENTIST, CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK: Now, this is the mirror. KAYE: The dolphins can't see us, but Reiss can study how the dolphins react to the mirror. REISS: We used...

Words: 454 - Pages: 2

Free Essay

Make Friends

...I’ll teach you know what to look for and how to effortlessly gain rapport with anyone. When you are with someone you trust, you may not notice, but you are naturally mirroring him or her. Mirroring is defined as when you copy someone else’s behavior; their movement, body position, hand gestures, tone of language, etc. A clear example of mirroring is seen when a couple naturally completes each other’s sentences. They are so in tune they actually seem to read the others thoughts. What most people do not realize is that mirroring is a two way street. You can actually mirror a person slightly and get them to feel closer to you naturally. When mirroring people it is very important that it stays outside of their perception. Be very subtle by copying breathing, the speed in which they are talking, and a few of the phrases they are using. Don’t make it obvious that you are mirroring them. The first thing you want to mirror...

Words: 1776 - Pages: 8

Free Essay

Soc 312

...themselves. Antonio’s poem, “Bully in the Mirror”, displays the how agents of socialization influence one’s “looking glass self” and how the look glass self once realized impact “answerability” and one’s desire to change. When students such as Antonio began to seek change in who they, are educators must be prepared to support this change as bullying is an epidemic is schools and students should be aware of its impact in every aspect. Antonio is a child that has been a bully for quite some time. He has come to realize that he does not like the person that he has become and wants to change. Antonio is alone as he makes this clear that he has no friends. The looking glass self is basically how we view ourselves based on our reflection of personal qualities and impressions of how we believe others perceive us (Kenny, R., 2007). As theorized by Cooley socialization coincides with the looking glass self (self-image) which is developed by “the imagination of our appearance to the other person; the imagination of his judgment of that appearance, and some sort of self-feeling of pride or mortification" (1964:184)” (Kenny, R., 2007). Antonio, in his mirror reflection, has come to see that those around him don’t like who he is as a bully and no he is perceiving himself in the same way that others do which is why he is crying out for help in changing what he now sees in himself as well as what other see in him. “I am a bully how could this be. The mirror is starting to Change...

Words: 338 - Pages: 2

Free Essay

Précis

...100 Word Précis Theme – social flow The Mirror City is a self-reflect place. It can be a personal space, and also be a place that interact random people at the same time, which is like a network, Facebook. In the mirror booth, the mirrors surround people, and the booth reflects them, so it can be own personal space. Basically, the main idea (or the inspiration) comes from a basic structure of a social network, ‘Facebook’. I applied the structure that people are visiting their own space through the other space ‘The Mirror City’ is a self–reflecting piece of art. When people observe own reflections through the mirrors, they are free to maintain own personal space in that section of mirrors. Also, this effect can also work when many random people to interact at the same time. This social network can be similar to an actual existing online network like, Facebook. The major concept of the project is determined by getting inspired from a basic structure of a social network, ‘Facebook’. Basically, moving through from one space to another. In the Mirror City, the mirror spaces are linked by the wooden path each other as a network. Just like how in facebook, a person can meet a random person through their friends, and their friends and so on. For architectural inspirations, R.O.M (Royal Ontario Museum); the sharpness and freewheeling shape and use of reflective material. Marinabay Sands Hotel in Singapore; the way of layering the ceiling is consulted as an...

Words: 255 - Pages: 2